Medical Ethics in Neonatal Care



Medical Ethics in Neonatal Care


Jonathan M. Fanaroff


This chapter explores the complexity of moral problem solving in neonatal medicine. First, principles of medical ethics and key terms and concepts are defined, followed by the application of these concepts in specific moral problems that arise (1) when a pregnant patient refuses treatment, (2) in the prenatal consultation at the limits of viability, and (3) when withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining medical treatment in the neonatal intensive care unit (NICU) is undertaken. A collaborative, procedural framework for consensual end-of-life decision making is described, and specific ethical issues that may arise in end-of-life care are discussed, including the use of analgesic agents, brain death and organ donation, palliative care, and the withdrawal or withholding of artificial nutrition and hydration. This chapter includes guidelines for ethical conflict resolution and an approach to the conduct of clinical research. Finally, a brief summary of ethical responsibilities of neonatal physicians is presented.


Three elements characterize the practice of medicine that are timeless, universal, and irrefutably true: (1) the fact of illness and the vulnerability it creates, (2) the act of the profession (the use of medical skills for the benefit of the patient), and (3) the practice of medicine itself—that which physicians and patients do together in the clinical encounter, characterized by mutual intentionality.69 These three elements are well exemplified in the care of sick newborn infants, in which the vulnerability of anxious parents is manifest, the clinical competence and moral discretion of health professionals are used for the benefit of newborn patients and their parents, and the practice is carried out in a patient-parent-physician relationship characterized by mutual trust and pursuit of the neonatal patient’s and parents’ good.


Medical ethics involves the systematic, reasoned evaluation, and justification of the “right” action in pursuit of human good or well-being in the context of medical practice. It involves a critical examination of the concepts and assumptions underlying medical and moral decision making, and it may include a critical examination of the kind of person a physician should be.73 Medical ethics has become a central focus in the practice of neonatal intensive care because it contains all the elements of moral discourse but without clear-cut “right” answers. Numerous ethical issues arise as physicians attempt to determine what is right and good for their vulnerable patients, physicians and parents deliberate on what constitutes the “best interests of the infant,” and NICUs use their technological capability in the quest for medical progress.


These issues are compounded by the fact that the treatment occurs in a fast-paced environment that precludes or severely limits opportunities for in-depth exploration of parents’ and physicians’ views and values. Increasing restrictions on resident duty hours and frequent changes in the on-service attending sometimes make it easier to focus on the next blood gas rather than the bigger picture. Care is also complicated by the medical uncertainty surrounding accurate outcome prediction of potentially adverse findings and by the very nature of many decisions in which quality of life and life itself may be under consideration. All these issues make the NICU a challenging, highly scrutinized environment in how ethical issues are examined, reasoned, and justified, and raise fundamental questions about what the responsibilities of neonatal health care providers should be.


Ethical issues may be experienced as moral dilemmas, moral uncertainty, or moral distress. A moral dilemma is present when the physician believes there is an obligation to pursue two (or more) conflicting courses of action. Because only one of these courses can be pursued, the physician has to make a value-based choice that compromises one of these obligations. A classic example in neonatal care is a conflict between action required by the principle of respect for autonomy and action required by the principle of beneficence.


Moral uncertainty typically arises when the presenting issue is unclear. Parents whose fetus has a major congenital anomaly are presented with the option of terminating that pregnancy or anticipating major surgery for their infant at the time of birth. They are unwilling to end the pregnancy, but are uncertain about the varying prognoses given to them by respective physicians. They, and possibly their care providers, remain unclear and uncertain about the principles and values that are in conflict.


Moral distress arises when the decision maker feels certain about the morally right thing to do, but this perceived “right” course of action is precluded for numerous reasons, including the caregiver’s lack of decision-making authority or institutional or financial constraints. Neonatal nurses who have intense hands-on contact with newborns may feel powerless and experience moral distress when treatment decisions are made by others.38 Ulrich and colleagues85 have elucidated the feelings of powerlessness, frustration, and fatigue experienced by nurses and social workers in relation to ethical issues in their workplace. The number of surveys of neonatologists’ preferences and practices at the limits of viability is also likely a reflection of a degree of moral distress within that group, as is the more personal, plaintive, and painful expression of the neonatal fellow in dealing with an infant “abandoned in the NICU” when faced with parental insistence on “doing everything” possible for a severely compromised and socially vulnerable infant.13



Principles in Medical Ethics


Ethical reasoning requires an understanding of the fundamental principles that define a domain (Box 4-1). Beauchamp and Childress have described four core bioethical principles: autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. It is useful to consider how these principles apply with respect to the care of newborns. Although reference to principles serves as a useful checklist of moral concerns, appealing to principles per se in the clinical context can be of limited value when the problem revolves around a conflict in the principles themselves. In many cases, a “principalis” paradigm may not do justice to the nature or complexity of the moral problem. In addition, in a purely principle-based approach, the role of the neonatal health care provider as moral agent (i.e., someone with personal virtues and values and the opportunity to take action that comports with that judgment of morality) is not highlighted. This chapter does not prescribe adherence to any particular ethical theory, but aims to enhance appreciation of the language of ethical discourse to enable nuanced reflection, reasoning, and ethical decision making, and to underline the role of the health care provider in these situations.




Autonomy


The principle of autonomy supports the right of competent patients to make their own health care choices. An individual who makes an autonomous choice acts intentionally, with understanding and without external controlling influences.10 An idealized expression of autonomy occurs when a competent adult chooses voluntarily and intelligently from among various options whose relative risks and benefits have been fully explained to him or her by the physicians (i.e., via a truly informed consent process).


The term parental autonomy is often used in the context of neonatal care without making a distinction between that term and parental authority, although most argue that autonomy can strictly be used only when making decisions for oneself and that parental authority is the more correct term when referring to the role of parents in decision making for their newborn infants. The use of parental autonomy may be appropriate, however, when a parent has a vision of what it means to be a good parent, and it is necessary for that parent to choose to be allowed to parent in that self-directed way.


There are at least two primary reasons why neonatal health care professionals should show respect for parental authority/autonomy: (1) because of the presumption that parents will make decisions that are in their child’s best interests, and (2) as a means of promoting a shared decision-making model with physicians. Physicians need to be conscious of the impact of their authority and the power that derives from expertise or that follows from information given in a convincing manner. They also have to recognize that parents’ ability to reason and to act in a self-directed way is often challenged in the presence of serious illness in their newborn infants.


Not everyone wishes to be the primary decision maker, and indeed there is a body of evidence that sometimes the prevailing bioethics emphasis on autonomy and self-determination is overwhelming to parents.66,92 Numerous studies show that respect for mothers’ or parents’ autonomy does not require physician adherence to a strict informed consent interaction; a more nuanced application of this respect can be satisfactorily achieved by including parents in decision making within a trusting parent-physician relationship.44,65 This inclusion may be more important than the parental “right” to make the final decision per se. Parents’ insistence on their right and role as final decision maker may become their stance only after a breakdown in communication or when respect for their role in a shared decision-making process has been disallowed or denigrated.


Too rigid or simplistic an interpretation and application of respect for parental autonomy by physicians is also problematic, such as when agreeing to a parental statement that “we want everything done.” Without exploring what underlies this declaration, physicians may neglect the complexity of the situation and the underlying parental fear of “abandonment.”30 Finding the right balance between respect for parental autonomy and the physician’s role and responsibility in any decision-making process requires insight, empathy, and great analytical and communication skills.



Beneficence


Beneficence is the obligation of health care providers to “do good,” that is, to promote the best interests of their patients. In newborns, this obligation is embodied in the concept of the “best interests of the newborn.” This is a moral and legal standard of judgment that helps to establish the primacy of duties to infants, ensuring they be regarded as fully human individuals with interests, even when clearly unable to express their own value system. Pursuing a course of action in the best interests of an infant implies determining what treatment course has a more favorable benefit-to-harm ratio than other possible options—whether the treatment is likely to improve the newborn’s condition or well-being, prevent it from deteriorating, or reduce the extent or rate at which it is likely to deteriorate, and whether the newborn’s condition is likely to improve, remain the same, or deteriorate without the treatment. It also requires consideration of whether a less restrictive or less intrusive treatment course would be as beneficial as the treatment that is being proposed.


Determination of best interests requires an assessment of the child’s potential quality of life. Quality-of-life considerations encompass the predicted cognitive and neurodevelopmental outcome, the potential for motor disability or other physical handicap (e.g., vision, hearing), and longer-term concerns such as behavioral and learning difficulties or school problems. It also considers the requirements for repeated or prolonged hospitalization, surgery, or medication, and the potential for pain and suffering to be endured. Quality-of-life considerations may also include less concrete medical states, such as the capacity for meaningful and potentially enjoyable interaction with other people and the environment.


The standard of best interests of the newborn acts as a threshold for judgment, yet the subjective nature of this assessment and the fact that the assessment is being done by surrogate decision makers must always be recognized. Additionally it is imperative for clinicians to be aware of their limited powers of prognostication. Repeated studies by Meadow and colleagues have shown that when health care professionals predict that an infant will not survive to discharge, they are incorrect relatively frequently. The procedural question of who are the rightful decision makers is of pivotal importance when parents, physicians, and nurses have different assessments of what is in the infant’s best interests. Consider parents who believe in the preservation of life regardless of their infant’s neurodevelopmental outcome; their perception of the benefits and harms of aggressive intervention may be quite different from the perception of a physician who places greater value on quality of life and relief of suffering. The best interests standard is not only a standard of judgment, but also a standard for possible intervention, if it is perceived by rightful decision makers that the infant’s best interests are not being served by a particular course of action. Diekema has suggested that the more conservative “harm” principle be applied in overriding parental wishes. By this principle, rather than determine the “best interests,” a harm threshold will be determined below which the parents’ decision will be overruled.22


In most jurisdictions, the state confers the responsibility for health care decision making on the parents of young children because parents have a unique relationship with their children—one of concern, obligation, responsibility, and intimacy. Recognition of parents’ moral authority in decision making presumes that parents would normally act to promote their children’s best interests and endeavor to make health care decisions in that light.


The concept of best interests engenders much debate, not only because of the subjectivity of its assessment, but also because some authorities believe the concept is too complex. Defining “best” may be unattainable; it is culture specific, it is too individualistic, and it ignores the interests of others. The concept does imply, however, that the child’s best interests should be pursued, even sometimes to the exclusion of family interests. Other authorities argue that it is legitimate for physicians and parents to consider family interests in making health care decisions for a sick newborn.35 It has been shown that most neonatologists ascribe to an incorporation of family interests into decision making for their incompetent patients.34


Despite these definitional difficulties and suggested alternative standards such as the “harm” principle, “best interests of the newborn” is accepted as a guiding principle for decision makers to use because it unites under one standard different meanings and exhibits reasonableness, given the prevailing conditions.48 Properly understood, the concept can serve as a powerful tool in settling disputes about how to make good decisions for individuals who cannot decide for themselves.



Nonmaleficence


The principle of nonmaleficence implies an obligation not to inflict harm on others. It has been closely associated with the maxim primum non nocere (first do no harm).10 Although beneficence incorporates preventing and removing harm as part of promoting “the good” of a patient, the injunction not to inflict harm remains a distinct principle and requires intentionally refraining from actions that cause harm. Such harm is generally interpreted as physical harm, especially pain, disability, or death. Nonmaleficence requires that no initiation or continuation of treatment be considered without regard to the infant’s pain, suffering, and discomfort; in situations in which a treatment is perceived as overly burdensome or harmful without foreseeable benefit, it should not be undertaken. This is especially relevant given a historical context in which attention to pain in neonates has been sorely disregarded, to the degree in which surgeries were performed without anesthesia.



Justice


Justice is the dominant principle relating to social cooperation. It is expected to determine how social benefits, such as health care, are distributed via justified norms that are the product of human choices and values. Although justice is regarded as a guiding principle for any health care system, no single simple, ideal implementation of it can suffice or satisfy all who wish to receive resources and be treated in ways that safeguard their rights. Generally, concepts of justice range from the broader utilitarian calculus to promote the greatest good for the greatest number in underwriting the distribution of resources (macroallocation) to a more narrowly focused equality of opportunity for each individual (microallocation). Justice in the distribution of resources would require that (1) patients in similar situations have access to the same health care, and (2) the level of health care available for one set of patients takes into account the effect of such a use of resources on other patients.


Reasoning in the context of allocation of resources for the individual patient allows that fairness is an important consideration, but is not the fundamental standard in this interaction. Microallocation issues are very rarely appropriate at the bedside, although some consistency between macrodistribution and microdistribution must exist if the two systems are to operate smoothly because the two are inevitably linked.


In every system, the provision of neonatal services requires guidelines to be developed for determining appropriate use of these costly and often limited resources. Priorities must be set and justified by authorities in decision-making positions. Any changes in the way neonatal care is delivered also need to be fair and accessible, and open and challengeable. Disputes should be worked out based on the acceptance of objective measures and trust in the integrity and fairness of the process and the individuals responsible for management of the process. The United States has recently seen justice principles fiercely debated as the country debated questions of whether health care was a “right,” the extent of individual versus societal responsibility for health care, and who should pay for health care. With greater attention being paid to health care costs, there is little question that how resources for sick newborns are used and justified may become more critically and ethically questioned.



Key Terms and Concepts


Communication with Parents


Parents require complete and truthful information about their infant—the diagnosis and prognosis, the available treatment options (including, where relevant, the option of no treatment), the benefits and harms associated with each option, and the limits of available technology. The manner in which this information is communicated influences parents’ understanding of the situation, their ability to discuss moral issues and values openly, and their ability to participate effectively in a decision-making process (Box 4-2). Information communicated in an honest and respectful manner is likely to foster trust; information that is confusing, incomplete, evasive, or conveyed in a hurried or dismissive way will engender mistrust. Transparency in communication is crucial: It emphasizes the physician’s reasoning, builds an understanding of the illness, makes the connection between data and their implications, and tempers unrealistic parental expectations.45



Box 4-2   Guidelines for Respectful Communication with Parents




Create an environment for communication that encourages parents’ participation and their becoming as fully informed as possible.


Identify and remove barriers that limit parents’ role in communication (e.g., language, physical distance).


Communicate with parents: at the time of admission, at any crisis point in their child’s NICU course, via periodic reviews of longer stay patients, and other unstructured opportunities.


Encourage parents to seek clarification of information at any point by requesting an appointment with the child’s responsible physician.


Provide open, truthful communication at all times.


Provide information as accurately as possible and with as much certainty of diagnosis and prognosis as is possible in each clinical situation.


Identify areas of medical uncertainty.


Use easily understandable language, and pay attention to health care “literacy” issues.


Assess family communication preferences, and attempt to communicate within those parameters.


Be pre-emptive in communication (i.e., foresee what problems or issues may arise in the child’s course).


Be proactive in communication in any clinical situation in which a poor outcome is predicted.


Convene meetings with both parents when important decisions need to be made.


Keep parents informed of any special investigations/tests that are planned in the course of management of their child.


Recognize the need for time to process and absorb information.


Ensure consistency and continuity of communication in the face of medical staff changes and handovers.


Practice open, honest, and timely disclosure regarding medical error.


NICU, Neonatal intensive care unit.


As medicine advances, physicians and parents must sometimes struggle with information that is at the limits of medical knowledge and in which the implications of findings are uncertain. The manner in which medical uncertainty, specifically prognostic uncertainty, is (or is not) communicated is extremely important and influences subsequent decision making. Neonatal physicians have been described as dealing with prognostic uncertainty via one or more of three strategies: (1) a statistical approach, (2) a wait-until-certainty approach, or (3) an individualized prognostic approach.74


With a statistical approach, decisions are made on the basis of an analysis of the known outcomes of infants with that condition—whether extremely low gestational age or a major chromosomal or congenital anomaly. The primary objective is to avoid enhancing the survival of infants with conditions in which the known outcome data show profoundly poor prognoses, even if this means that some potentially viable infants do not survive.


The wait-until-certainty approach begins with treatment for almost every infant with any chance of survival. It establishes a momentum in favor of continuing treatment until a major medical event does or does not occur. The possibility of withdrawal or discontinuation of life-sustaining medical treatment is considered only when severe, adverse medical findings become unequivocally evident. A problem with this strategy is that frequently, even with the passage of time, uncertainty persists. The issue is not certainty per se, but rather the degree of certainty required by physicians and parents to facilitate decision making. This approach denies the ethical complexity of situations by failing to address the moral and the medical uncertainty; it risks relegating parents and other members of the health care team to the role of bystanders as the medical course unfolds.


With an individualized prognostic strategy, treatment is initiated for all infants who have a reasonable chance of survival. Decision making solely on the basis of biomedical factors is avoided, and the ongoing moral responsibility of the decision makers is emphasized in an effort to involve parents and the health care team in navigating the ensuing prognostic uncertainty. This approach avoids the extremes of either withholding treatment from all infants who fall below a minimum threshold or treating all infants until the outcome is absolutely certain.


The timing of any communication with parents is crucial. Ideally parents’ readiness to receive information and their coping resources should be ascertained so that appropriate information is shared with consideration of their adaptation to the medical setting. In acute situations, if an urgent decision is required, the physician needs to move the relationship rapidly, however, from one of “moral strangers” to one in which moral issues can be openly discussed.


Obtaining parental consent for each planned intervention for the infant is often the prompt for communicating with parents in the NICU. Some authorities may regard that obtaining formal, informed consent from parents for virtually every neonatal test or procedure is a means of maintaining a high standard of ethical care. Ensuring that parents are kept up to date and advised of treatment plans is important; however, information gathered from an ethnographic study showed that parents did not want to be asked to consent to every procedure.1 They often felt overwhelmed when asked to consent for routine and minor procedures and felt they were given the illusion that they could or should say stop when there was no real choice and no time to learn more about each procedure. It was also clear that the more the staff offered information and time to listen to parents when not driven by a consent process, the easier it was for parents to discuss questions and dilemmas on fairly equal terms. When consent was required, parents emphasized the need for a two-way informed agreement between fairly equal partners with established mutual trust and respect.


A sound patient-physician relationship is a sine qua non of good medicine, for it is within this relationship that physicians exercise their humanity, understanding, and respect for the values of others. Every communication interaction with parents is an opportunity for relationship building. The ideal model in adult patient-physician relationships is considered to be the deliberative-interactive model, wherein physicians not only help the patient with clarification of his or her values, but also strive to make their own reasoning transparent for the patient to appreciate the many factors that inform their professional recommendation.25 In neonatal medicine, the physician’s communication relationship is with the parents (or legal guardians) of the newborn, and the optimal parent-physician relationship aims to mirror the deliberative-interactive model, wherein physicians provide parents with accurate and timely information (with as much medical certainty as possible), and encourage and empower them to identify their values and treatment preferences. This model of relationship respects parental authority, encourages the physician’s expression of his or her own clinical judgment, and, in so doing, promotes the best interests of the newborn and the family.


Environmental and contextual factors challenge the achievement of this parent-physician relationship, including the fast NICU pace and the demands of time and scheduling changes. There may also be personal physician-related factors that need to be overcome, such as physicians’ reluctance to express their views, a focus on short-term goals, an inherent avoidance of prognostication and discussion about outcomes, and a fear of damaging the relationship by being the bearer of bad news. Nevertheless, it is incumbent on physicians to attempt to develop a therapeutic alliance with parents and to engage in relationship building with them. The responsibility for a parent-physician relationship always rests with the physician.



Teams and Communication


Although it is important that the responsible physician attempt to integrate all of the important information and maintain a consistent relationship and pattern of communication with parents, neonatal intensive care is provided by many clinicians with expertise in different fields. This situation requires an understanding among the team members of the differences in responsibility in communication with parents, such as when conveying day-to-day quantifiable, objective information, or when communicating severe diagnoses or the more speculative, prognostic significance of specific findings. Although the responsibilities of each discipline are generally known, in certain situations communication boundaries may need to be defined to minimize fragmented and inconsistent information. Interdisciplinary meetings, in which all the practitioners involved with the patient share their findings and perspective, are crucial in ensuring that consistent patterns of communication are maintained.


It is sometimes said that the ability to communicate is innate. This is not, however, borne out in the literature. For both family and team interactions, it needs to be understood that communication is a primary skill that can and should be improved and developed throughout one’s career.



Family-Centered Neonatal Intensive Care


Family-centered care is a philosophy that acknowledges the sick newborn infant’s place within the social unit of the family. It also acknowledges that cultural, emotional, and social support by the family is an integral component of the infant’s care. Family-centered care shapes policies, programs, facility design, and day-to-day interactions, but should reflect values and attitudes just as equally as protocols. The potential benefits of a family-oriented approach include improved parental satisfaction with care and decision making, decreased parental stress, greater parental ability to cope with their infant’s appearance and behavior, improved success with breastfeeding, and increased parental comfort and competence for post-discharge care.23


Recognition of the child’s place within the family highlights the cultural, religious, and spiritual dimensions of families’ lives and may bring to light significant diversity within these domains. In a pluralistic society, parents and physicians are unlikely to share the same values, cultural systems, personal histories, and experiences, and at times of stress these differences may present health care providers with significant challenges.


The first challenge is to recognize, understand, and respect the cultural, religious, and spiritual views and values of parents and families. Meeting this first challenge is crucial because misperceptions caused by a lack of sensitivity can lead to inappropriate care or poor clinical outcomes. Cultural competence is more than sensitivity to cultural norms different from one’s own. Cultural competence implies an ability to interact effectively with people of different cultures and comprises four components: (1) the individual’s awareness of his or her own cultural worldview, (2) the individual’s attitude toward cultural differences, (3) the individual’s knowledge of different cultural practices and worldviews, and (4) the individual’s cross-cultural skills.57 Developing cultural competence results in an ability to understand, communicate with, and interact effectively with people across cultures.


The second challenge for neonatal health care providers involves the limits of tolerance—where to draw the line between accepting patterns of decision making between couples or within families that contrast markedly with the prevailing cultural norm of shared parental responsibility for decision making. A third challenge arises because not only are parents and physicians products of their own respective cultures, but also their interactions occur within a further “culture”—that of medicine and intensive care itself—with its own values, assumptions, and understanding of what should be done.


Although the health care team should recognize how families’ interests are shaped by social, cultural, and other contexts, it is important not to stereotype the members of specific social, cultural, ethnic, or religious groups. Individuals’ affiliations may not be predictive of their beliefs and values in the care of their infant, and the health care team should regard each patient and family as unique and attend carefully to their specific views and values.


When attentiveness to the views and values of families is difficult because of language barriers, professional interpreters should be used. Use of an interpreter is advisable for three reasons: (1) it ensures that parents’ views are available to the health care team, (2) it removes the burden on family members or friends for the transfer of information, and (3) it limits the potential for miscommunication. In certain situations, a cultural interpreter not only can facilitate language comprehension, but can also provide useful information about cultural norms and traditions that are unfamiliar to the health care team. Access to high-quality interpretation services is an essential component of ethically and culturally sensitive care that also satisfies a regulatory requirement and decreases medicolegal risk.


Religion and the more general concept of spirituality as a major determinant of culture, tradition, and family values often needs to be addressed with parents, particularly when end-of-life decision making is undertaken. A qualitative questionnaire study completed by parents after their child’s death revealed the emergence of four explicitly spiritual/religious themes: prayer, faith, access to and care from clergy, and belief in the transcendent quality of the parent-child relationship that endures beyond death.75 Other significant themes with a religious/spiritual dynamic included finding meaning, hope, trust, and love. Similar findings were obtained in a study focused on the delivery room consultation: Mothers stated that religion, spirituality, and hope were the major factors that guided their decision making.12 The implication of these studies is that health care teams need to consider whether they have or need to create an environment that is hospitable to, and supportive of, religious or spiritual practice, that clinical staff recognize parents’ spiritual needs and provide access to hospital chaplains and community clergy, and, on a deeper level, appreciate parents’ religious and spiritual perspectives in prenatal consultations and end-of-life discussions.




Team Consensus in Ethical Issues


How teams that normally function synergistically in terms of purely medical matters operate when dealing with ethical issues may be very challenging, not only because of the difficulty in defining roles and responsibilities in matters of ethical deliberation, but also from a more fundamental aspect in that the two major professions, medicine and nursing, have differed over time in their preparation for this practice.81 Medical professionals tend to view their role as one in which the best science is in the patient’s best interest, with less attention to deeper questions such as the goals and limits of medicine and the moral core of the profession. Seeing things from the patient’s point of view, relating to the patient’s family in a nonjudgmental way, emphasizing the healing potential of communication, and having respect for patients’ informed choices seem to be more intrinsic to the nursing tradition. In interactions concerning the end of life of a neonate, physicians see the focus of their moral obligations on decision making with parents, whereas neonatal nurses see their moral obligations focused on the process and moment immediately surrounding death.26 What is needed, according to Storch and Kenny,81 is “shared moral work”: Interprofessional practice implies that individual health care practitioners are aware of their own professional values and the need to work collaboratively, build understanding, and work toward resolution with other professionals, particularly when different perspectives threaten team function. The beneficial effects of multidisciplinary participation and perspectives have been well shown in teams developing guidelines for decision making, such as those at the limits of viability.9,43

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Jun 6, 2017 | Posted by in PEDIATRICS | Comments Off on Medical Ethics in Neonatal Care

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access