Clinical Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynecology

56 Clinical Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynecology


Hugh E. Mighty and Jenifer Fahey


There are times when physicians are called upon by their patients or colleagues to help make difficult medical decisions. There also are times when physicians may disagree with decisions that their patients or colleagues have made. In either case, the physician must be able to analyze the situation in a systematic fashion in order to provide advice in a way that promotes the patient’s best interest. Preparing medical students to take on this professional responsibility should be an essential goal in medical education.


This chapter provides a brief overview of clinical ethics, including a review of core principles of medical ethics followed by a section on common ethical dilemmas that are specific to the field of obstetrics and gynecology. It also includes representative case studies to highlight relevant points and provides students with some general guidelines for ethical decision-making.


Medical Ethics


Background


Ethics is the branch of philosophy concerned with the study or evaluation of human behavior/conduct to identify the norms, rules, values, and principles that guide our moral life. Medical ethics is an example of “applied ethics,” in which these values, norms, or principles are used to guide decision-making in actual cases where the best course of action is not clearly evident. Because medical knowledge often is not enough to guide medical decision-making, it is important for health practitioners to have an understanding of key concepts in the field of ethics, and learn how to conduct a careful and disciplined analysis of ethical dilemmas that may confront them in the clinical arena.


Western medical ethics traces its roots to antiquity and the beginning of the Hippocratic tradition, which emphasizes the concept of duty to patient and provides guidelines for physician behavior when interacting with patients. Many of the same core concepts of medical ethics found in the earliest writings on the subject can be found in the Code of Ethics of the American Medical Association (AMA), first adopted in 1847. In the 1970s, Beau-champ and Childress published their seminal modern text on medical ethics, The Principles of Biomedical Ethics, in which they identify beneficence, nonmaleficence, autonomy, and justice as the four, core moral principles of biomedical ethics. Since then, a principle-based approach (also known as “principalism”) has come to dominate the medical ethics arena.


A common criticism of this principle-based approach, however, is that although it provides a helpful way to study an ethical problem, it is of limited use in guiding decision-making in clinical practice. This is due, in large part, to the fact that in many clinical cases these principles are actually in conflict with one another, and there is no clear hierarchy among them to help resolve such ethical dilemmas. Furthermore, the principle-based approach relies heavily on moral rules and theories but underemphasizes contextual issues, such as gender relations, standards of practice, economics, cultural considerations, and legal issues, which affect both patient and provider decision-making.


In such situations, the clinician may have to draw on other resources or theoretical frameworks to help guide decision-making. A summary of some of the moral theories that guide medical ethics is included in Table 56.1.


Principles of Medical Ethics


Regardless of the criticisms of a principle-based approach, beneficence, nonmaleficence, autonomy, and justice are still widely accepted as core principles in medical ethics. A brief definition of these four principles can be found in Table 56.2 and below in more detail.




























Table 56.1 Examples of moral theories
Virtue ethics Moral conduct should be guided by virtues such as kindness, compassion, respect for others, etc.
Professional ethics Moral conduct should be guided by the standards that are outlined by accredited/well-trained group of professionals
Utilitarian ethics Moral conduct should be guided by the balance of the total good or total bad consequences of actions in a way that maximizes good/value
Kantian ethics Feminist ethics Moral conduct should be guided by the acceptability of an action if this action were generalized to all similar situations
Feminist ethics Moral conduct should take into account gender considerations to ensure that there is not harmful gender bias in one’s actions
Rights-based ethics Moral conduct should ensure that basic individual rights (autonomy, privacy, confidentiality) are upheld
Communitarian ethics Moral conduct should ensure that communal values are upheld


















Table 56.2 Core principles of medical ethics as they pertain to the physician’s actions
Autonomy The physician should respect the right of the patient to make decisions regarding their care
Beneficence The physician should act in a way that promotes the patient’s best interests and promotes patient wellbeing
Nonmaleficence The physician should avoid harming the patient
Justice The physician should give the patient what is his or her due and should treat similar patients equally

 


Autonomy

Autonomy, or self-rule, in the context of ethics is the quality of moral independence. In the realm of medical ethics, it is manifested as the right to make one’s own decisions. To be an autonomous entity the individual must be: (1) free from coercion or other controlling influence or influences, and (2) possess the capacity for “intentional action.” Respect for autonomy in medical decision-making is understood to mean that if these two standards for autonomy are reasonably met, the individual has the right to make decisions regarding their medical care, even if the decision conflicts with what the provider believes is in their best interest.


The term “reasonably” is used because humans are rarely fully free of controlling influence. So, although a provider may not always be able to determine whether a patient is truly an autonomous entity, he or she should make a reasonable effort to determine whether there are controlling influences that significantly compromise the patient’s autonomy. It is also understood that a physician should not take actions that exert a controlling influence on the patient.


There are many times when treatments and procedures will compromise the capacity for intentional action. Self-administration of narcotics or other psychotropic medications are good examples. Thus, the patient should not be asked to make medical decisions in this compromised state. Furthermore, it is clearly unethical to purposely compromise a patient’s capacity for intentional action with this compromised capacity being the end goal. It is the principle of autonomy, and the obligation to try to ensure that the patient is an autonomous entity, which underlies the concept of informed consent. Informed consent is a central concept to ethical decision-making, which is discussed in detail in Chapter 55 and 57.


Beneficence and Nonmaleficence

The obligation to do good (beneficence), along with the obligation not to infict harm on others (nonmaleficence), are closely related principles that are central to medical ethics. Their importance to medical ethics dates back to antiquity, when it is believed that Hippocrates (or one of his students) included them in the oath taken by new physicians, now commonly known as the Hippocratic Oath. Included in the same statement within the oath is the principle of justice: “I will apply dietetic measures for the benefit of the sick according to my ability and judgment; I will keep them from harm and injustice.”


If medicine is the science and art of promoting health and wellbeing by treating, alleviating, and curing disease, it can then be argued that beneficence is the driving ethical principle of medicine. However, all ethical principles, including beneficence and the obligations derived from these principles, are bounded and sometimes even overridden by other principles and obligations. Quite often, for example, the obligation to “do good” for a patient, which is derived from the principle of beneficence, comes into conflict with an obligation derived from another key ethical principle—the obligation to respect patient autonomy.


Justice

Justice is the concept of giving to each person what is his or her due. In the realm of medical ethics it includes the obligations to provide to each patient that to which he or she is entitled, to allocate resources fairly, and to treat all patients equally. It is a complex principle prone to the effects of context and individual bias, including the physician’s background and experience.


What is perceived as just by an individual or group of individuals can vary greatly from what others may believe to be just. Furthermore, in a system of unequal distribution of resources, the physician is handicapped in his or her ability to be truly just. For example, regardless of severity of disease, patients with health insurance will often have access to care more readily than those who do not.


In nonemergency situations, the physician has an obligation to promote the wellbeing of each individual patient, and is not expected to take into consideration these system-wide dilemmas of distributive justice during individual clinical encounters. However, advocating for a just allocation of health care resources and not taking actions that compound inequalities in our health care system are ethical obligations of the physician. In emergency or mass casualty situations, however, physicians will have to take into consideration the limited availability of resources and make decisions as to whom to treat and in what order.


In addition to the principles outlined above, there are values or “moral rules” that also are an important part of ethical decision-making and behavior in the medical arena. These include, but are not limited to, veracity (telling the truth); respect for patient’s privacy, confidentiality, and dignity as well as professionalism, compassion, and collegiality. Some of these concepts are also discussed in more detail in Chapter 55 on communication and provider—patient interactions.


A number of professional medical organizations and associations have created documents that translate these principles and moral rules into prescriptive statements on physician conduct, ethical medical decision-making, and provider—patient relationships. The AMA’s Code of Ethics included in Table 56.3 is an example of such a document. The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) also has a Code of Ethics, which is very similar to that of the AMA.


































Table 56.3 The American Medical Association’s Code of Ethics
I A physician shall be dedicated to providing competent medical care, with compassion and respect for human dignity and rights
II A physician shall uphold the standards of professionalism, be honest in all professional interactions, and strive to report physicians Deficient in character or competence, or engaging in fraud or deception, to appropriate entities
III A physician shall respect the law and also recognize a responsibility to seek changes in those requirements which are contrary to the best interests of the patient
IV A physician shall respect the rights of patients, colleagues, and other health professionals, and shall safeguard patient confidences and privacy within the constraints of the law
V A physician shall continue to study, apply, and advance scientific knowledge, maintain a commitment to medical education, make relevant information available to patients, colleagues, and the public, obtain consultation, and use the talents of other health professionals when indicated
VI A physician shall, in the provision of appropriate patient care, except in emergencies, be free to choose whom to serve, with whom to associate, and the environment in which to provide medical care
VII A physician shall recognize a responsibility to participate in activities contributing to the improvement of the community and the betterment of public health
VIII A physician shall, while caring for a patient, regard responsibility to the patient as paramount
IX A physician shall support access to medical care for all people

Reproduced with permission from American Medical Association Code of Medical Ethics Chicago, Ill: American Medical Association, 2008


 


Ethical Dilemmas in Obstetrics: the Fetus as Patient


Maternal Autonomy vs. Fetal Beneficence


Ethical decision-making in obstetrics and gynecology is complicated by several factors that are peculiar to the field. The most significant of these in the practice of obstetrics is that the provider is simultaneously caring for two patients—the mother and the fetus—both of whose interests the provider owes a duty to protect. The moral obligation due to the fetus, however, is generally accepted within the context of medical ethics to be different from that owed to the mother.


It has also been generally accepted that the obligation owed to the fetus by the physician changes as the fetus advances in gestation, especially as it reaches and passes the threshold of viability. Chervenak and McCullough (see Further Reading) have written extensively on the subject of the fetus as patient, and propose that the viable fetus is a fetal patient and that the previable fetus is a fetal patient only when the woman confers such status on it.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Jun 6, 2016 | Posted by in GYNECOLOGY | Comments Off on Clinical Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynecology

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access